Assume there is an element f that is in all the other primes Q1 Q2 Q3 etc of σ(J). In other words, f is in each Qi, and not in any Pi. The intersection of the primary ideals under Pi equals the saturation of J with respect to f.
This is practically a corollary of the previous theorem, which completely characterizes the saturations of J. The powers of f cannot lie in one of our primes Pi, else f lies in Pi. Thus the multiplicatively closed set seeded by f misses our designated primes, and collides with the other primes. Saturation by f produces the intersection of our designated primary ideals. But we would like to establish a specific power of f, so there is a little more work to do.
Let x lie in each Hi below Pi. Consider an off prime Qi. Since f is in Qi, which is the radical of its Hi, some power of f winds up in Hi. When this is multiplied by x, the result lies in Hi.
Switch to a prime Pi in our set. Now x already lies in Hi, so x times f0 lies in Hi. Put this all together and a sufficiently high power of f, say fn, takes x into each primary ideal, and into J.
Notice that n does not depend on x. Every x in the intersection of the designated primary ideals is driven into J by fn.
Intersection agrees with saturation in the fraction ring, whose denominators are powers of f. Expressed another way, the intersection is the conductor ideal [J:fn].
Such an f must exist. Suppose it does not. Let W be the intersection of the prime ideals Qi, the "other" primes. Clearly W is in each Qi. If any part of W misses all the primes in Pi, we have found our element f. Thus W is contained in the finite union of prime ideals Pi, and W lies in exactly one of them.
Let W lie in P3. Thus the intersection of the primes Qi lies in P3. This means some prime, say Q7, lies in P3. However, all the primes contained in P3 are part of our designated set. We have reached a contradiction, hence there is an f that meets our criteria. We can use this f to saturate J, and obtain the intersection of our primary ideals.
As a special case, suppose all the primes in σ(J) are in our designated set. There are no "other" primes, and f is not well defined. However, we don't have to saturate J at all, because J is already the intersection of the designated primary ideals. Set f = 1, and the theorem is satisfied.